How humans relate to nature

What is the goal of conservation biology or environmental activism? (Or to put it more generally, what is our obligation toward nature?) If the goal is to preserve nature in as pristine a state as possible, untouched by humans, how does this account for the fact that humans are not separate from nature but rather a part of it? This afternoon I heard a lecture by J. Baird Callicott, a noted environmental philosopher, about this question. (The talk was organized by Indiana University’s Poynter Center for the Study of Ethics and American Institutions.)

Callicott outlined some of the attitudes toward humans and nature over time; most relied on some kind of metaphysical essential attribute of man that separated him from nature. Man was created in the image of God, for example, or man was the rational animal. Darwin turned this kind of thing upside down when he said that our supposedly unique capabilities (e.g., for speech or intelligence or ethics) evolved over time from proto-capabilities in other species. This idea that there is no boundary between us and other species is central to Aldo Leopold’s land ethic, which “changes the role of Homo sapiens from conqueror of the land-community to plain member and citizen of it.” (Quote from A Sand County Alamanc)

But, as Callicott stated the resulting paradox: “If Homo sapiens is a part of nature, then human actions, no less than the actions of other species, are natural–just another intriguing chapter in the biography of the earth, no more subject to ethical praise or condemnation than the actions of other species.” And of course many of us would take vigorous exception to that idea, which has consequences for how we treat the land and the creatures we share it with. (In his book Conversations with the Archdruid, John McPhee quotes Floyd Dominy (former Commissioner of Reclamation, and big on dams) as saying: “Nature changes the environment every day of our lives–why shouldn’t we change it? We’re part of nature.”)

Callicott found a resolution to the paradox by considering the various time scales operating in nature, from the organismic (operating at the level of the individual organism, and including processes of metabolism and photosynthesis), to the ecological (processes of succession and disturbance), climatic, evolutionary, and geomorphological. The processes of the organismic scale range in duration from one day to about a thousand years, of the ecological scale from one year to thousands of years, and so on, with each scale having a longer timespan. Geomorphological cycles are the longest of all, some of them stretching into the billions of years.

Humans speciated on the evolutionary time scale, and evolved the capacity for culture on the same scale, which places humans and human culture both within the time scales of nature. But human culture, once launched, is Lamarckian (relying on the inheritance or transmission of acquired or learned characteristics) rather than Darwinian, and thus operates on a much shorter time scale (and Callicott presented a brief summary of weapon technology to illustrate that it’s not only faster, it’s speeding up these days).

And this is where the resolution of the paradox arrives: we cross the boundary between human and nature when we begin to “transform ecosystems faster than other biota can adapt.” So we are a part of nature, not set apart by God or by our special abilities or by something in our essence like our rationality; but at the same time we are not free to do whatever we want and claim that all our actions are natural and thus value-neutral and not subject to moral judgment. We need to act appropriately with respect to the spatio-temporal scales of nature.

Well, there it is in a nutshell; the talk lasted an hour, with half an hour of question-and-answer afterward, so this is just a sketch, but it should give you the gist of it. I found it a reasonably coherent way to resolve something that I have puzzled over. I need to think about it some more, but this certainly gave me some ideas to chew over (and some more ideas for books to read). Some interesting questions came up afterward, including one about practical recommendations arising from all this. He gave several examples of ways to make our footprint smaller, e.g., vegetarianism (not for the sake of livestock, who might not be alive at all if we weren’t raising them for food, but for efficiency of land use–since we get relatively little food out of animals for each pound of grain we put in, it would be more efficient to eat lower on the food chain–which frees land up to go back to an uncultivated state). He mentioned an initiative he’s involved in in Denton, Texas, where he lives, to concentrate development so as to leave room for green space. (If it can happen in Texas, he said, it can happen anywere.)

I’d be very interested in hearing anyone else’s thoughts on this subject. Like I said, I’m still chewing it over myself.

2 Comments

  1. The other approach is to say that an event being “natural” has no intrinsic importance in our moral reaction to it. These problems come up in other situations, too… for instance, the field of evolutionary psychology has gotten a lot of flak for a paper (or papers, don’t recall offhand) in which it was suggested that both rape and infidelity may be adaptive traits in human men. Evolution being a major part of nature, “adaptive” is only a few steps off from “natural”, so the outcry came up because saying a trait is adaptive was interpreted as saying it’s natural and therefore immune from criticism. Similarly, diseases are natural. Rather than trying to come up with a way to draw a line between the natural and unnatural in order to justify moral response to things we don’t like, it seems simpler to me to just say that since we are part of nature, there’s no reason to split off nature as some sort of moral no-man’s-land. Once you get rid of the natural/unnatural dichotomy you can also avoid one of the major problems of the environmental movement–it’s often interpreted as being about nature vs. people, with the environmentalists on the side of nature and the developers and industrialists, therefore, on the side of people. Instead, the real situation is that environmentalism is pro-human in terms of long-term survival and happiness of humans, whereas the growth-for-growth’s sake industrialist approach is pro-human only in terms of temporary wealth and is not in any way motivated by an interest in overall human survival or happiness. Pollution isn’t bad because it’s unnatural, pollution is bad because it’s anti-human as well as anti-everything-else. The same goes for overgrazing of the southwest US, deforestation, etc., etc. The problem isn’t unnatural actions, it’s actions that prioritize short-term greed over all else. For instance, the problem with Floyd Dominy’s viewpoint isn’t that dams are unnatural, it’s that dams destroy ecological processes we rely on (the Aswan High Dam in Egypt being the best example–a civilisation fed for millenia on flood sediments is seeing its agricultural capacity collapse because of flood control) while providing benefits that are often minor or nearly nonexistent (how many dams in the west were built with the interests of only a few wealthy agriculturalists in mind?).

    Well, anyhoo, before I spend my day writing I’ve got to go study some grasses…

  2. I’ve thought a lot about that connection people like to make between naturalness and morality, but I hadn’t thought of it in this particular context before. This gives me something new to add to my thinking about both areas. And that’s a good point about pollution, etc., being bad not because they’re unnatural but because they’re harmful to living things. I think it was my friend Mark who said that economy and ecology are really based on the same things, and it’s only the time scale we think at that puts them into conflict.

Leave a Comment

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *

This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed.